I had been told that Euclid proved things, and was much
disappointed that he started with axioms. At first I refused to accept
them unless my brother could offer me some reason for doing so, but he
said, "If you don't accept them we cannot go on", and I wished to go
on, I reluctantly admitted them pro tem. The doubt as to
the premises of mathematics which I felt at that moment remained with
me, and determined the course of my subsequent work.
Bertrand Russell: Autobiography, volume 1 page 32
There is the other possibility; that we die into an absolute reality wich we call God, because we still have no better name for it. This alternative too cannot be proved nor of course can it be refuted. Here every human being is faced with a decision that no one can take away. We have no rational proof for eternal life. But - as I have already said - we do have reasonable grounds.
I'm breaking into this paragraph to dispose of the illusion of absolute proof, something which atheist-materialist most extraordinarily of all, devotees of scientism inevitably demand of all religious statements.
I say it is most extraordinary in those who express a belief in scientism, the claim that only those things demonstrated by science are admissible as knowledge and, especially, in the extreme cases from the stupidest of sci-ranger comment thread trolls to eminent scientists holding enormous public repute, university positions, are members of National Academies of Science and are given medals and cash awards by the awards giving establishment. To start with, and as I've noted before, their own claim is not a statement of science or demonstrable by science, so it is one of a long series of self-contradicting holdings of that most widely held of atheist faiths.
What is extraordinary about them demanding absolute proof or absolute rejection of statements is that, as one of their most illustrious figures, Bertrand Russell should have faced the fact that no such thing as absolute proof exists in even that most exacting of sciences in which something approaching absolute proof can be attained, mathematics. His adult work with his teacher, the far more admirable thinker to my thinking, Alfred North Whitehead sought to find such absolute proof of the universally held findings of mathematics only to have their enormous effort made somewhat moot by reviewers of it, most notably in the famous incompleteness theorem of Kurt Godel, which was confirmed and extended by some of the most eminent younger mathematicians in the 20th century.
In the physical sciences, especially in the two most successful of those, physics and chemistry, the practical consequences of the non-existence of absolute proof has characterized their entire history. The 19th century gradually showed the limits of the proofs of the greatest of all physicists, so far, Newton and the successors of that framing of physical reality, have demonstrated that though they might get very good at predicting things, their knowledge about even the very simplest seeming of objects is never absolute. That has not kept them from making the most ridiculous statements about coming up with a "theory of everything" and closing the system of physics, something which the experience of mathematicians dealing with a far simpler and more precisely defined universe in the 20th century should have clued them in is an absurd quest and an even more ridiculous claim to still be making.
There are still many crucial aspects of chemistry which are not knowable, I was reading about the form new compounds will crystallize into a while back and why those cannot be predicted.
As the sciences deal with far more complex entities and events the unattainable goal of absolute proof grows ever more distant until it disappears EXCEPT IN THE DISHONEST PRESENTATION OF EVEN ENTIRELY UNGROUNDED SPECULATION IN THE SAME LANGUAGE THAT NEWTONIAN PHYSICS MIGHT HAVE BEEN BY A MATERIALIST OF THE MID-19TH CENTURY. What you often hear announced on NPR as scientific knowledge any given morning is as likely as not to have a status far more like 19th century phrenology than it does modestly stated and much more reliable physics.
But that is something that scientists should have known before they were credentialed by the colleges and universities that gave them their BS degree. It is something which an atheist, Joseph Weizenbaum said as well as I've ever seen it said:
The man in the street surely believes such scientific facts to be
as well-established, as well-proven, as his own existence. His
certitude is an illusion. Nor is the scientist himself immune to the
same illusion. In his praxis, he must, after all, suspend disbelief in
order to do or think anything at all. He is rather like a theatergoer
who, in order to participate in and understand what is happening on the
stage, must for a time pretend to himself that he is witnessing real
events. The scientist must believe his working hypothesis, together
with its vast underlying structure of theories and assumptions, even if
only for the sake of the argument. Often the "argument" extends over
his entire lifetime. Gradually he becomes what he at first merely
pretended to be; a true believer. I choose the word "argument"
thoughtfully, for scientific demonstrations, even mathematical proofs,
are fundamentally acts of persuasion.
Scientific statements can never be certain; they can only be more
or less credible. And credibility is a term in individual psychology,
i.e.. a term that has meaning only with respect to an individual
observer. To say that some proposition is credible is, after all to say
that it is believed by an agent who is free not to believe it, that
is, by an observer who, after exercising judgement and (possibly)
intuition, chooses to accept the proposition as worthy of his believing it.
How then can science, which itself surely and ultimately rests on vast
arrays of human value judgments demonstrate that human
value judgments are illusory? It cannot do so without forfeiting its
own status as the single legitimate path to understanding man and his world.
To which I say, Amen, until the last sentence. Science cannot honestly assume that status, even Weizenbaum in his radical modesty over-reached. There are facts of history which are far more reliably known to be absolutely true than even very reliable science can achieve.* Even Weizenbaum as he was disproving the pretenses of scientism couldn't keep himself from asserting that superstition. The status that scientists love and even demand is, itself, an illusion.
There is no choice in even dealing with the physical realm but to rely on something other than proof, not less than because absolute proof is not something we can even know is possible except as an imaginary goal. "Reasonable grounds" is, actually, what we really depend on in life and, as Weizenbaum notes, that is, itself, dependent on the choice to believe.
Hans Kung continues.
We can commit ourselves to this in enlightened reasonable trust. Truly, not to console ourselves with the promise of an afterlife, but to set ourselves all the more decisively in the here and now, in this life, in this present-day society. And that we do not die into nothingness but into God seems to me to be more reasonable; it seems more reasonable under any circumstances. Think; if God really exists and if he really is God, he cannot be merely the God of the beginning, but must be the God of the end. Then he is our Finisher as well as our Creator. And it is he alone, the Creator and Preserver of the cosmos and of human beings, who can be expected to have one more word to say, even in dying and at death, beyond the frontiers of all that has hitherto been experienced; to have the lat word, just as he had the first. If I seriously believe in an eternal, living God, I believe also in God's eternal life, in m own eternal life. So if I begin my profession of faith with belief in "God the almighty, the creator" I may very well finish it with belief in "life everlasting".
As I said yesterday, my primary focus in this commentary is political, in how to get the most people to treat others as they would want to be treated, even when they would rather not treat them in such equality. So my interest in discussing the belief in the afterlife is related to the character of that future in light of it's tendency to produce good works. I do believe that history shows that there is all the difference in the world to a society where many people believe and put the commandments of Jesus, the teachings of the Prophets into effect in their lives and the laws of their countries. Where people became convinced that The Bible, especially the "golden rule" mandated that people not be held in slavery, that led to abolition, even having that influence on secularists who could find no basis for that in the science they were coming to consider an absolute authority. Where people didn't accept that as an absolute moral requirement - EVEN WHEN THEY DIDN'T WANT TO TREAT SOME PEOPLE AS THEY WOULD WANT TO BE TREATED - slavery persisted and expanded. I think in variations limitless, almost all problems of government, politics, law, are inevitably related to that commandment and its implementation. If everyone always did it, the law, even governments would be superfluous. However, we do not live in such a world. Jesus said he didn't have a kingdom of this Earth.
This statement by Kung contains the central conviction that I base a belief in an afterlife on,
Then he is our Finisher as well as our Creator. And it is he alone, the Creator and Preserver of the cosmos and of human being.
I think the afterlife is too much separated in our imagination from the present life. Modern cosmology holds that our being here, put in terms of mathematical probability of a myriad of physical constants and conditions being precisely tuned to allow for intelligent life, is exhaustively improbable, requiring an enormous exponent of 10 to be expressed as a ratio of one. The afterlife's seeming improbability would seem to be matched with a similarly large improbability of present life. But we're here and so we don't think of that in the same way.
I suspect that our lack of understanding of our present life and its relation to God is far greater than we suspect, as well. Every atheist argument of that, from comparing us to the myriads of microorganisms too the vast and innumerably starred universe matches a scale of human understanding of all of it out of human limitations and imagining that all of reality exists on that anthropomorphic scale. Making man the measure of all thing is the ultimate sort of conceit that atheists accuse religion of, especially the monotheistic traditions derived from the far more modestly and carefully expressed Hebrew Scriptures. Those scriptures, despite being told in human experience, never to my knowledge make man the measure of all things, it explicitly cuts us down to size as compared to God, even as it asserts that God regards us and, even, that God regards all of life, even noting the fall of a sparrow.
When someone asked Marilynne Robinson what she expected heaven to be like, she broke the dead silence that fell over the auditorium after a few seconds by saying, "I expect to be impressed." I expect to be surprised. If I'm wrong, I don't think I'm going to have to get over the disappointment for long.
* I think the pretense of the attainability of absolute knowledge having in peoples' experience been serially thwarted by such things as news reporting of the absurd claims made by credentialed scientists, most glaringly and ridiculously in the fields of nutrition and health, has certainly contributed to such things as anti-vaccination mania. It has also contributed to such things as climate change denial, though in that case the manipulation of people through lies freely broadcast in the libertarian mass media is more important to consider. The denial of reality of the Trumpian kind is more related to that though the impossibility of achieving the golden fleece of absolute proof plays a part in that, as well.
I don't care enough to research the question, but almost immediately I wonder how Russell got around Descartes cogito, and the problems of extreme skepticism Descartes outlined in his Discourse.
ReplyDeleteEverything starts with an assumption, and of course the serious problem Russell ran into was the idea he could establish a body of knowledge which was without assumptions (axioms), yet Godel proved decisively any formal system (which is what Russell was seeking) can generate questions it cannot answer.
So what's the point of being so rigorous, if such logic fails at some point? Aside from the fact you can't fail to make some assumptions, as Descartes pointed out.
I was tempted to try to find my moldy old copy of Russell's History of Western Philosophy to read the chapter on Descartes but I can't remember where I put it - never got around to arranging my books that well. It's an interesting question and since all I'm looking forward to today is processing apples and tomatoes while I listen to the hearings, here's something from the Stanford Encyclopedia
ReplyDeleteIf the cogito does not presuppose a substantial self, what then is the epistemic basis for injecting the “I” into the “I think”? Some critics have complained that, in referring to the “I”, Descartes begs the question by presupposing what he means to establish in the “I exist.” Among the critics, Bertrand Russell objects that “the word ‘I’ is really illegitimate.” Echoing the 18th century thinker, Georg Lichtenberg, Russell writes that Descartes should have, instead, stated “his ultimate premiss in the form ‘there are thoughts’.” Russell adds that “the word ‘I’ is grammatically convenient, but does not describe a datum.” (1945, 567) Accordingly, “there is pain” and “I am in pain” have different contents, and Descartes is entitled only to the former.
One effort at reply has it that introspection reveals more than what Russell allows – it reveals the subjective character of experience. On this view, there is more to the experiential story of being in pain than is expressed by saying that there is pain: the experience includes the feeling of pain plus a point-of-view – an experiential addition that’s difficult to characterize except by adding that “I” am in pain, that the pain is mine. Importantly, my awareness of this subjective feature of experience does not depend on an awareness of the metaphysical nature of a thinking subject. If we take Descartes to be using ‘I’ to signify this subjective character, then he is not smuggling in something that’s not already there: the “I”-ness of consciousness turns out to be (contra Russell) a primary datum of experience. Though, as Hume persuasively argues, introspection reveals no sense impressions suited to the role of a thinking subject, Descartes, unlike Hume, has no need to derive all our ideas from sense impressions. Descartes’ idea of the self does ultimately draw on innate conceptual resources.
I'm at the point where I think all such dealing in the "ultimate" stops in a dead end or a cul de sac. There's no getting past the requirement to make a choice, even what we pretend to know is a result of such unadmitted choices.
Oh, I just noticed the date so I looked up the citation at the Stanford Encyclopedia, that is from Russell's History of Western Philsosophy.
DeleteI read that while I was in full thrall to the Russell legend, it's one of the books that, as I read more about the actual substance, it's flaws expanded to the point where I wouldn't trust a thing he said without fact checking. I see just about everything he did after the critics of the Principia Mathematica started tearing it apart as totally flawed by his ideological preference. I haven't read as much of Alfred North Whitehead but I don't find his later work smells of ideology to that extent.
The reference to Hume raises the issue of "I" that crossed my mind in reading your quote about Descartes. Russell, not surprisingly, misread Descartes, who accepts the "axiom" of "I" because without it, what can be known, and how? June's argument that all we are us sense impressions still assumes an observer, a perceiver, of those impressions. Otherwise we have only the metaphor of the TV running in an empty room: if no one is there to see/hear it, is it creating a sense impression? Or even the illusion of self-awareness?
ReplyDeleteDescartes cogito expressly accepts the presumption of a self because without it, what can one know, or be assured one knows?
"June" should be "Hume." I blame auto-correct.
ReplyDeleteIt's my experience that auto-correct is not. And it's getting worse.
Delete